Several months ago, I attended a meeting of the American
Genetics Association organized by Robin Waples in Seattle, Washington. The theme
for the meeting was “Evolution and Plasticity: Adaptive Responses by Species to Human-Mediated Changes to their Ecosystems.” The meeting was a particularly
clear example to the current excitement about the role of plasticity (including
epigenetics) in the evolutionary process – an enthusiasm that really
crystalized around Mary Jane West-Eberhard’s “Developmental Plasticity and
Evolution”. Much of the excitement centers around the idea that plasticity (a
single genotype has different phenotypes in different environments) can promote
evolutionary change. For instance, plasticity can provide the raw material necessary
for evolutionary change by revealing otherwise cryptic variation. In addition,
plasticity might generate immediate adaptive phenotypic shifts that allow individuals
and populations to persist in new environments, thus allowing and promoting
subsequent adaptation (without the initial adaptive plastic shift, the
population would have gone extinct). This idea is not new, having originated
with James Baldwin in 1896, but it has certainly become vastly more popular of
late.
These (and other) ideas for how plasticity might promote
evolution are certainly interesting, but how does one go about testing them? One
of the things I found simultaneously most interesting and frustrating about the
Seattle meeting was that seemingly any pattern in the data was being
interpreted as evidence that plasticity promotes evolution. Perhaps most
commonly, a finding that plastic responses to a particular environmental difference
were in the same direction as evolved differences between populations evolving
under the same environmental difference was interpreted as evidence that
plasticity promoted evolution. For instance, guppies might shoal more in the
laboratory when exposed to predator cues and guppy populations evolving with
predators might shoal more than those evolving without predators (independent
of proximate predator cues in the laboratory). On the exact opposite hand,
however, evidence that plastic responses to a particular environmental
condition were in the opposite direction as evolved differences was also interpreted
(by other presenters) as evidence that plasticity promoted evolution. In this
case, the idea is that the plasticity is likely maladaptive and so requires
evolutionary compensation.
The current inferential scheme for whether or not plasticity promotes evolution |
In
the past, when I pointed out to some ecologists that competition seemed of
little importance as a mechanism determining a particular species'
distribution, they often gave the following answer. The reason, they said, for my
inability to find evidence for competition was because it had already been eliminated
by past coevolutionary divergence between those species. However, for the
reasons discussed in this paper, and until some strong evidence is obtained
from field experiments along the lines suggested above, I will no longer be
persuaded by such invoking of "the Ghost of Competition Past". (Connell 1980 –
Oikos)
Although
the Seattle meeting ended several months ago, I was just prompted to write
a post about the topic owing to the recent publication in Nature of another
study about the role of plasticity in evolution: “Developmental Plasticity and the Origin of Tetrapods.” Em Standen,
Trina Du, and Hans Larsson wanted to test whether plasticity would promote
major evolutionary transitions, especially the transition from swimming in water
to walking on land. To test this possibility, they invoked a classic hypothesis
test: if an ancestral species shows adaptive plasticity in response to an
environmental shift, and that plasticity mirrors the evolutionary changes that
accompanied the environmental shift, then plasticity likely promoted the
transition. Specifically, they reasoned that rearing an air-breathing fish out
of the water (by misting them regularly) would cause developmental changes in
morphology that would lead those fish to be better walkers out of water. If so,
the same thing may have taken place in the water-to-land transition. This is a
cool idea – although, of course, plasticity in the ancestor is merely consistent
with the hypothesis rather than proof of it.
The difficulty in any such study is that the actual ancestor (here
the ancestor of land-dwelling tetrapods) is not accessible for study – and so
Standen and colleagues needed an analog species. Coecocanths obviously wouldn’t
work and lungfish are just too pathetic on land. So the authors chose to use
another basal tetrapod – the Polypterus or “bichir.” Performing the experiment,
they found that Polypterus raised out of water were indeed better at walking
out of water than those raised in the water (see the cool video below) and showed
developmental morphological changes that were similar to those in the fossil
record associated with the move out of water.
This result is fascinating and I was privileged to see its
implementation as the work was done in the lab of my close colleague Hans
Larsson. In fact, I was able to talk to him about it multiple times on the
train on the way to work. In addition to simply be jealous that I hadn’t
thought of it first, I came to crystallize a particular criticism of the work.
Specifically, I contend (if only as Devil’s Advocate) that the results could just
as easily be interpreted as showing that developmental plasticity does NOT
promote evolution. The reason is that Polypertus has never made the transition
to land despite millions of years of opportunity to do so. Thus, all this
wonderful plasticity did NOT accomplish the task it is inferred to assist.
Given all these flexibility in ad hoc interpretation, it seems to me that the field needs a critique and a careful (a la Connell) outline of the various patterns that might be observed in an experiment and what inferences they would and would not allow. Until such an endeavor is undertaken and adopted, inferences about plasticity are simply too plastic.
I wrote the above on the train
a few seats away from Hans and, while then walking to work, we discussed what
the optimal experiments would look like. We think that the ideal approach would
be experimental evolution: have replicate plastic and non-plastic genotypes/populations,
expose them to new conditions, and track their subsequent evolutionary
trajectories. If the most plastic genotypes show the fastest and most dramatic evolution,
then plasticity promotes evolution. If the least plastic genotypes show the
fastest and most dramatic evolution, plasticity constrains evolution. If plastic
and non-plastic genotypes don’t differ, plasticity does not influence
evolution. Until then, I will no
longer be persuaded by such invoking of "the Ghost of Plasticity
Past".
"If either of two opposite patterns is interpreted as evidence for the same thing (i.e., plasticity promotes evolution, albeit in different ways), how do we proceed with rigorous hypothesis testing. Surely we also need a set of results that would be interpreted as evidence that plasticity does NOT promote evolution. That is, the hypothesis must also be clearly falsifiable through some particular outcome in the data."
ReplyDeleteIt seems entirely possible that plasticity in the "right" direction promotes evolution, and that plasticity in the "wrong" direction also promotes evolution; it could be that both are true (or it could be that both are false). The right question seems to be to compare the outcome with plasticity to the outcome without plasticity, as you get to later in the post.
Another thing that might need emphasis is the distinction between "promoting evolution" through accelerating the rate of evolutionary change, versus "promoting evolution" through decreasing the risk of extinction. Plasticity could have effects on both of these things, and they might not be in the same direction, right? So even if plasticity in species A slows down the rate of evolutionary response compared to non-plastic species B, for example, species A might ultimately adapt more quickly than species B, paradoxically, because populations of species B subjected to the new environmental condition might evolve quickly, but then go extinct before they make it out of the hole. Slow and steady wins the race?
Indeed. What we need is a clear decision key for this field1
ReplyDeleteSinead Collins here reports on a study that uses the "ideal experiment" described at the end of the post. http://ecoevoevoeco.blogspot.ca/2014/09/the-ideal-experiment.html
ReplyDelete